In my previous post, I explained how I Yoram Hazony linked nationalism with conservatism in his new book, Conservatism: A Rediscovery. Today I’ll look at the premises for the conservative paradigm he offers. He is somewhat hesitant in doing so, because the lessons and experience of history on which conservatism rests are not things that easily reduce to simple premises for the sake of forming tidy syllogisms. However, he acknowledges that this gives liberalism an argumentative advantage, in that liberalism can easily be “reduced to a small number of clearly articulated premises, which are easy to summarize and teach, even to children.” Conservatives hesitate to summarize the conservative outlook in this way, because the “reduction of any worldview to a number of explicit premises invites rigidity and dogmatism, even as important matters go unmentioned.”
Nonetheless, Hazony feels it a necessary task to attempt. He first gives the premises animating Enlightenment liberalism:
- All men are perfectly free and equal by nature.
- Political obligation arises from the consent of the free individual.
- Government exists due to the consent of a large number of individuals, and its only legitimate purpose is to enable these individuals to make use of the freedom that is theirs by nature.
- These premises are universally valid truths, which every individual can derive on his own, if he only chooses to do so, by reasoning about these matters.
A different paradigm is offered by Hazony’s summary of conservative premises:
- Men are born into families, tribes, and nations to which they are bound by ties of mutual loyalty.
- Individuals, families, tribes, and nations compete for honor, importance, and influence, until a threat or common endeavor recalls them to the mutual loyalties that bind them to one another.
- Families, tribes, and nations are hierarchically structured, their members having importance and influence to the degree they are honored within the hierarchy.
- Language, religion, law, and the forms of government and economic activity are traditional institutions, develop by families, tribes, and nations as they seek to strengthen their material prosperity, internal integrity, and cultural inheritance to propagate themselves through future generations.
- Political obligation is a consequence of membership in families, tribes, and nations.
- These premises are derived from experience, and may be challenged and improved upon in light of experience.
We can see major differences between these two worldviews. For example, while liberalism rejects the idea that we can have obligations to which we never voluntarily consented, conservatism teaches that “Political obligation, whether to one’s family, tribe, or nation, does not arise from consent but from the bonds of mutual loyalty and gratitude that bind us to the other members of such loyalty groups, including especially the past generations that built up what we have and was handed down to us…mutual loyalty – which is largely inherited, rather than chosen – is the primary force that establishes political order and holds its constituent parts in place.”

In keeping with conservative reasoning, Hazony argues the conservative premises are not abstract principles derived from reason. They are simply what the experience of history shows to be empirical facts about how human societies are formed and maintained. It is by losing this historical grounding that “rationalist political theory has failed”, because its “premises are constructed without reference to experience. For example, experience suggests that Men are born into families, tribes, and nations to which they are bound by ties of mutual loyalty. Wherever we look, throughout history and in every corner of the globe, we see that mutual loyalty or group identification is the strongest force operative in politics, pulling individuals tightly together, forming them into families, clans, tribes, and nations…It is the cause that establishes tribes and nations, states and empires, making them the stable and enduring entities that are the subjects of competent political philosophy.”
Hazony is unimpressed with the Enlightenment liberal premises, stating that “None of these premises is empirically true” and in fact they utterly fail to describe “empirical human nature in general. There is no historical context in which these premises can be said to have been true. Nowhere in history do we find conditions in which all human beings, or even most, are capable of attaining universal political insight by means of reason alone; are blessed with perfect freedom and equality; are without membership in, and obligation to, any political collectives except those they have consented to join; and live under a government whose sole purpose is to enable them to enjoy their freedom. And if these things are not empirically true in even a single case, they cannot serve as the foundations for a political theory whose purpose is to understand the political world.” If liberal premises are not derived from experience, on what basis to liberals suppose them to be true? To the rationalist liberal, the premises can be known through pure reason. To conservatives such as Hazony, this “pure reason” is little more than idle speculation at best.
Hazony gives no quarter to those who would claim the premises of Enlightenment liberalism are meant as normative principles to guide behavior rather than empirically validated descriptions of human experience, saying “an argument does not become a competent exercise in ‘normative political theory’ by detaching itself from everything we know about human nature and political order from experience” and that attempting to make this move is “just playing at make-believe.” An empirically derived fact of how human societies work, Hazony says, is that “it is the existence of a certain relation between the individual and the family or nation to which he belongs, and not anyone’s consent, that is the source of his obligations to his family or nation, as well as of the obligations of his family and nation toward him.”
Because the nation is a system of mutual loyalty and mutual obligation, rooted in shared history and experience, many programs supported by liberals serve to undermine the health of the nation by undermining these necessary bonds. An unyielding commitment to free trade, says Hazony, leads “workers to regard themselves as betrayed” by both business leaders and policymakers as they are left unshielded from the effects of foreign competition, which has the effect of “bursting the bonds of mutual loyalty that had made America a cohesive and internally powerful nation.” Even if free trade is ultimately good for academic measures of economic growth, it comes at the cost of undermining the social cohesion that represents the true health and strength of the nation. There are, Hazony says, “obligations that exist between individuals who have been business partners of long standing, or between an employer and an employee of long standing, and here, too, the obligations that derive from these relations of mutual loyalty” are not reducible to something so simple as “the terms of a written contract.”
Liberals are also too sanguine about the effects immigration has on the social bonds nations need. While immigration can be beneficial to a nation if it’s maintained at a low enough level that immigrants are “willing to assimilate themselves into the language, laws, and traditions of their adopted nation”, when immigrants come too fast and in too large a group, they become “too large and internally cohesive” such that they “resist dissolution and begin to compete with the native population. This can result in open hatred, domestic tension, and violence.” But, says Hazony, Enlightenment liberal philosophy ignores these concerns. Because liberalism “does not recognize strong national and tribal loyalties as an important factor in political affairs”, liberal thinkers “cannot generate any real justification for maintaining what seems, from a liberal perspective, to be arbitrary curtailments of individual liberties” in the form of borders, leading liberals to a situation where “borders have come to be seen as though they have no purpose.”
To the conservative understanding of human nature and the nature of nations, however, borders are far from mere arbitrary impositions. To the conservative, borders “are a spatial expression of the bonds of mutual loyalty that hold nations together. An internally cohesive nation will establish borders to protect its people, its assets, its laws, and its traditions from being exploited and weakened by outsiders who are not bound to it by ties of mutual loyalty.”
In the next post, I’ll describe how Hazony views individual liberty, and how this idea is treated differently in the liberal and conservative worldviews.
READER COMMENTS
steve
Nov 15 2023 at 12:18pm
“Because the nation is a system of mutual loyalty and mutual obligation, rooted in shared history and experience”
Yet many of us have very different experiences and history. Loyalty and obligations are selectively honored or sometimes deliberately abandoned. I think you can create some idealized earlier world but if you look at reality it doesnt fit so well. There is always someone saying things were better in the past but it’s seldom the case, or maybe it was for a specific group of people but not everyone.
“between an employer and an employee of long standing, and here, too, the obligations that derive from these relations of mutual loyalty” are not reducible to something so simple as “the terms of a written contract.”
This really surprised me. H0noring those kinds of obligations has been pretty selective through history. There are examples of employers/land owners who treated employees well or at least decently but there are is also no shortage of examples where that did not happen. Again, he needs to selectively choose from the past.
Steve
Warren Platts
Nov 15 2023 at 12:55pm
Conservatism can be summarized in a single premise: “If there is no need to change, there is a need not to change.”
Thomas L Hutcheson
Nov 15 2023 at 6:47pm
If one feels bound to their countrymen by bonds of loyalty and affection, might they not endorse some economic policy (say free trade or immigration) that would benefit most even if it harmed a few. Might not the few that are harmed (like soldiers in battle) feel bound to assent to the policy because of their affection for the nation even at cost to themselves.
Roger McKinney
Nov 16 2023 at 12:11pm
Few people will recognize Hazony’s conservatism or liberalism. It takes a whole book to define them. Having defined them in his own peculiar straw man way, who cares?
Essentially, he asks us to ignore 300 years of economics advancements and revert to thinking like mercantilists.
Does he attempt to explain the hockey stick growth in living standards in the West?
Jon Murphy
Nov 16 2023 at 1:21pm
I agree with Steve’s comments above. I do not think the empirical record is as clear as Hazony wants to think.
Further, does he discuss at all what happens when these “bonds of loyalty” are in conflict?
JP
Nov 16 2023 at 2:40pm
Chesterton’s fence is a good starting point for understanding conservatism.
Richard Fulmer
Nov 16 2023 at 3:30pm
While Locke influenced other Enlightenment thinkers, “The Enlightenment” was not a single school of thought. Distinct, and often opposed branches, emerged including the French, Scottish, American, and German Enlightenments. Hazony concentrates on the French version and ignores the Scottish version, which was far more influential on American thought.
Jon Murphy
Nov 16 2023 at 4:14pm
Are these 4 points your interpretation or a direct quote? I’d argue Hazony is attacking one particular strand of Enlightenment (and, despite his claims to the contrary, one that goes to the principles of Americanism). The social contract theory of governance was rejected by many Enlightenment thinkers. For example, Adam Smith, David Hume, and Frederic Bastiat reject the “consent” argument for government, preferring for a broader “convention.” Smith, at the very least, and Bastiat also fully reconigize (and celebrate) the importance of things like family and other social groups on our morals, ideas, and behavior (Smith wrote a whole book about it: the Theory of Moral Sentiments). And yet, they were much more cosmopolitian.
Hazony is claiming to build off empirical evidence, but as Steve says, that evidence is not as strong as he thinks. More importantly, it seems like he is relying on pre-Enlightenment cases. One of the things about the Enlightenment is that it was trying to recon with a more cosmopolitian world: people were interacting more and more outside their bands. Enlightenment, then, was thinking about those relationships and the moral systems that developed.
In other words, I doubt Hazony’s analysis is really applicable to the modern world. Indeed, that may explain the significant failure of nationalism as a political ideology in the 20th Century.
Kevin Corcoran
Nov 16 2023 at 8:31pm
Those are a direct quote.
Yes, Hazony is specifically attacking the Enlightenment tradition of philosophical rationalism, which he identifies as a key component of the liberal tradition developed by various Enlightenment thinkers, particularly as exemplified by the work of John Locke. Hazony says:
Hazony’s interpretation of Locke as a “decisive figure in the liberal tradition” is not entirely idiosyncratic – for example, Don Boudreaux also recently said that Locke is “universally regarded as a founding philosopher of liberalism.” However, in that same post, Boudreaux also identifies (as do you) Adam Smith as a liberal. Hazony’s classification puts things differently. As you point out, Adam Smith is one thinker who rejects the Lockean-style argument about government, and by Hazony’s categorization, Smith counts as a conservative empiricist, not a rationalist liberal. As Hazony puts it:
So Hazony would agree with you that thinkers like Hume and Smith were engaged in “thinking about those relationships and the moral systems that developed.” The difference is that by thinking of things in that way, by means of evaluating real-world developments, Hazony classifies them as empiricist conservatives, not as rationalist liberals. As you note, thinkers like Smith and Hume rejected the Lockean framework – and by Hazony’s classification, this rejection of Locke’s framework and method of examination puts them in a fundamentally different camp than Locke. And because Locke is often regarded as the lodestar of the liberal tradition, by Hazony’s lights, neither Smith nor Hume would be classed as liberals.
Jon Murphy
Nov 17 2023 at 9:25am
Understood. Thank you for the clarification
Richard Fulmer
Nov 17 2023 at 1:48pm
And he’s correct; Locke *is* universally regarded as a founder of liberalism. But as I pointed out above, liberalism split into several branches. The French Enlightenment led to socialism and today’s progressivism. The Scottish Enlightenment led to the founding of America and (pre-Trump) American conservatism. Hazony’s case depends upon conflating the French and Scottish Enlightenments.
Danny
Nov 23 2023 at 4:37pm
‘All men are perfectly free and equal by nature.’
–is this sort of an idiosyncratic straw man, resembling as it does “All men are created equal”? Which is a phrase that can be interpreted in a variety of ways.
‘Political obligation arises from the consent of the free individual.’
Another straw man? Is there somebody who hasn’t read Hobbes?