Recently here at EconLog Scott Sumner and Janet Bufton have had an interesting discussion on liberalism as an antidote against authoritarianism (see Sumner here, Bufton’s comments here, and Sumner’s continuation here).  The central theme has been how liberalism, properly understood and consistently applied, helps inoculate one against a descent into authoritarianism, even if one likes what the authoritarian is doing.  They’re great posts and you should read them (even if you have already).  But I think there is a gap in the conversation that I wish to fill: what unique aspect of liberalism makes it an effective vaccine?  The liberal understanding of justice makes it an effective vaccine.

To be clear, I am sure both Sumner and Bufton are both aware that the liberal understanding of justice makes liberalism effective.  Justice is implicit throughout their posts.  I am just bringing it to the fore.

In this man’s opinion, the best development of liberal justice comes in Adam Smith’s Theory of Moral Sentiments.  In TMS, Smith discusses three understandings of justice.  The first he calls “commutative justice,” or “mere justice.”  Commutative justice has very precise rules about how to treat one another and they basically boil down to “don’t harm people and don’t take their stuff.” 

Like the rules of grammar, these rules of justice are foundational.  Under very rare circumstances (and even then most judiciously) they can be broken, but for the most part, they must be upheld.  The other two understandings are what he calls “distributive justice,” (which is using one’s talents and resources to the best of their ability), and estimative justice (which is giving a person or thing its proper due).  This development can be found on pages 269-270 of the Liberty Fund edition.  For my purposes here, I will be discussing exclusively commutative justice.

Justice is foundational.  No society can survive without justice.  Any society where different individuals are treated unjustly, where their person or property is under constant threat, will tend to extinguish itself, if not through in-fighting then through conquest or dissolution by more robust societies.  But justice itself is not sufficient to make a good society or a good person.  We need other virtues, like love, beneficence and benevolence.  A society that is simply just would not be a pleasant place to live.

But, as Smith points out, we are limited in our capacity to give love, beneficence, and benevolence.  We are limited by our own resources; it would be quite impossible to love everyone equally.  Such a burden is limited to God (or some other “all-wise Being.”)  Any attempt to love anyone and everyone the same would result in a person being immensely unhappy (see Part VI, Section II, Chapter III).  Consequently, humanity’s lot is far more simple: “the care of his own happiness, of that of his family, his friends, his country” (pg 237).  We love ourselves.  We love our family more than our friends.  Our neighbors more than our country.  And so on.  Our social circles determine who we love and how (for more on this, see Adam Smith and the Circles of Sympathy by Fonna Forman).  

So far, so good.  Even nationalists will tend to agree with this point.  What differentiates the liberal from the nationalist or authoritarian is the question, “What do we owe to each other?”  How do we treat people socially furthest from us?  This is where the matter of justice comes in.  

To the liberal, we do not owe many people love, benevolence, and the other virtues.  I am sure you, dear reader, are a lovely person, but I will simply never love you as much as I love my brother, mother, and father.  If my brother needs a ride to the airport, I’ll pick him up.  If you ask me, I’m charging a fee.  

But what we do owe to everyone, globally, is justice.  To not cause harm to their person or their property.  Smith’s famous “Chinese Earthquake” thought experiment (pages 136-137) demonstrates this point.  If an earthquake were to hit China tomorrow and a thousand people die, few people would lose much sleep over it.  Yes, we would sympathize with their loss, but our feelings would be only the smallest fraction of what those affected by the quake would feel.  One would lose more sleep over the loss of a pinky than the loss of those thousand lives.  But if the loss of a pinky could stop the earthquake from ever happening, then there becomes a strong feeling to lose one’s pinky and save the thousand lives.

The fact that everyone, whether they are in our social circles or not, is deserving of the bare minimum of justice is what separates liberalism from authoritarianism.  Liberal justice is not much, but it is powerful.  Authoritarians tend to divide up the world into categories.  Certain categories are deserving of justice.  Others are not.  Consequently, authoritarians conduct horrific and evil acts.  Liberalism, though its reminder that what we owe to everyone is merely justice, acts as an effective inoculation against a descent into authoritarianism.  Injustice, when recognized, is a powerful repulsive feeling.  We seek to stop injustice.  Liberalism helps us see those injustices being done.