
John Cochrane has an excellent post discussing Bob Lucas’s contributions to macroeconomics. Here’s a point that I also keep harping on:
The Fed often asks economists for advice, “should we raise the funds rate?” Post Lucas macroeconomists answer that this isn’t a well posed question. It’s like saying “should we cry wolf?” The right question is, should we start to follow a rule, a regime, should we create an institution, that regularly and reliably raises interest rates in a situation like the current one? Decisions do not live in isolation. They create expectations and reputations. Needless to say, this fundamental reality has not soaked in to policy institutions. And that answer (which I have tried at Fed advisory meetings) leads to glazed eyes. John Taylor’s rule has been making progress for 30 years trying to bridge that conceptual gap, with some success.
Lucas is the economist that launched the rational expectations revolution. Much of the skepticism about “rational expectations” comes from a lack of comprehension about what the assumption actually means. Here’s Cochrane:
But “rational expectations” is really just a humility condition. It says, don’t write models in which the predictions of the model are different from the expectations in the model. If you do, if your model is right, people will read the model and catch on, and the model won’t work anymore. Don’t assume you economist (or Fed chair) are so much less behavioral than the people in your model. Don’t base policy on an attempt to fool the little peasants over and over again. It does not say that people are big super rational calculating machines. It just says that they eventually catch on.
I’d like to illustrate the issue with a hypothetical example involving a big glass jar of jellybeans. You may recall a famous example cited in the “wisdom of crowds” literature, where an MBA class was asked to estimate the number of jellybeans in a large jar. Most of the guesses were far from reality, but the median guess was surprisingly close, say within 1% or 2%. In that case, how would I model the public’s jellybean estimates?
The least bad approach might be to estimate the actual number of jellybeans, and then assume that this figure was also the public’s estimate. This approach would not work perfectly, but it’s hard to see any alternative that would be better. Would you wish to assume the average guess is only 60% of the truth? How about 150%? If so, why?
Now suppose I ask a mathematician how many ellipsoids with dimensions of 9 mm long and 6 mm wide will fit into a cylinder that is 8 inches tall and has a diameter of 5 inches. The mathematician provides an equation that looks sort of complicated to the average person. Does it make sense to assume that the average person uses that equation when estimating the number of jellybeans? Obviously not. But that equation gives you a good estimate of the actual number of jellybeans, and if we have no reason to assume the public’s estimates are biased, then it also provides the best model of the public’s estimate.
Rational expectations models in macroeconomics are often full of scary looking equations. The modeler then assumes that the public’s forecast of variables such as inflation is “consistent” with the model. Thus if the model predicts 7% inflation, we don’t assume that the public forecasts 3% or 13% inflation—why would we? We assume that the public also expects 7% inflation. That may not be correct, but it seems the least bad approach unless we have specific knowledge that the public either over or under estimates the variable in question. (Unfortunately, this is hard to test, as inflation is poorly defined. The public’s estimates that show up in places like the Michigan survey probably reflect a definition of inflation that doesn’t include hedonic adjustments, and thus is a bit higher than the government inflation estimate.)
Many people reject rational expectations because it seems to suggest that the public is composed of super intelligent calculating machines. But that’s not at all what it means. Bennett McCallum suggested that it would have been better to call the concept “consistent expectations.” The claim is actually quite modest. All the rational expectations assumption says is that if your model specifically implies that X is true; don’t assume the public believes that X is false, at least not without evidence for that claim.
READER COMMENTS
David Seltzer
May 21 2023 at 6:17pm
Scott, it seems rational expectations are dynamic. If they are consistent, I would allow for Bayesian updating. To wit. Combining prior information with new data so as to generate a posterior distribution of expected outcomes.
Scott Sumner
May 22 2023 at 12:15pm
I agree.
spencer
May 22 2023 at 11:09am
RE: “if your model is right, people will read the model and catch on, and the model won’t work anymore.”
That’s what upset the cart for Joseph Granville. They anticipated his calls and ruined his signals.
What’s upset is Alfred Marshall’s cash balances approach. Turns will come somewhat earlier.
bill
May 22 2023 at 5:22pm
Why do you think Paul Krugman is so harsh on this?
https://twitter.com/paulkrugman/status/1660252645259452418
Scott Sumner
May 22 2023 at 11:16pm
He did the same sort of thing right after Friedman died. And this is reasoning from a price change:
https://twitter.com/paulkrugman/status/1660251944701575169
Interest rates do not measure the stance of monetary policy. Rates rose in 2022, yet monetary policy was expansionary.
bill
May 23 2023 at 5:47am
I had to chuckle at that link. I couldn’t imagine which parts were the contractionary ones.
Knut P. Heen
May 24 2023 at 11:31am
I think most of the skepticism comes from the fact that rational expectations make Keynesian economists redundant. The lightning calculator critique is merely a straw-man.
Nick Ronalds
May 24 2023 at 3:19pm
Good post. Yet books get written about how useless economics is because all those assumptions–such as of “rationality” of consumers and producers–obviously don’t describe the real world. Some of those books are written by economists, or at least people with Ph.D.’s in economics.